[FOM] Mathematician in the street
Vaughan Pratt
pratt at cs.stanford.edu
Fri Aug 28 21:25:58 EDT 2009
Bill Taylor wrote:
> Just a small quibble here, for Vaughn Pratt:
>
>> I would first ask the "street mathematician"
>> whether they regarded the concept of set as necessarily tied to
>> a particular formulation of mathematical language or whether sets
>> had an existence of their own independent of language.
>
> Isn't there a third plausible option?
>
> They may take it that the universe of sets does indeed have a fixed
> "Platonic" existence, but that nevertheless any attempt to deal with it
> necessarily requires one to view them as tied to a particular language.
This may be, but how would you go about arguing necessity here?
> Much in the same way that there is really only one concept of
> "effective computability", or of "a universal machine", or of
> Chaitin's constant; but that the particular implementation of it
> may seem quite different according to the technical substrate,
> which is essentialy unimportant, as they all lead to "the same thing".
Each of those examples admit sharpening with one or another theorem.
What theorem did you have in mind here?
Any given formulation of the interaction of word and object that
exhibits any interdependencies between them comes with some limitations,
otherwise word and object would be independent and it would be a theory
of noninteraction. As a simple example, let L be a set of assertions, W
a set of possible worlds, and |= a binary relation of satisfiability
defined as a subset of W x L, namely the set of pairs (w,p) such that p
holds in w.
Now with no other information about the detailed structure of L and W,
it is conceivable that there could be a proposition which is true in
every world, or that there could be a world falsifying every
proposition. However there could not be both, by the
irresistible-force-immovable-object paradox if you will.
Are the following two situations similarly incompatible?
(i) For every pair u,v of worlds there is a world u&v such that for
every proposition p, p is true in u&v if and only if it is true in both
u and v.
(ii) For every pair p,q of propositions there is a proposition pvq such
that for all worlds w, w satisfies pvq if and only if it satisfies at
least one of p or q.
The answer is that (i) and (ii) *are* compatible, but together they
impose the draconian restriction that L and W are both linearly ordered
by inclusion between the worlds satisfying them and the propositions
they satisfy, respectively. No strengthening of that restriction is
possible because it entails (i) and (ii): u&v can always be taken to be
the smaller of u or v while pvq likewise can be taken to be the larger
of p or q.
More startling is that this very unstructured framework of an arbitrary
binary relation of satisfiability between an arbitrary set of
propositions and an arbitrary set of possible worlds necessarily admits
an operation of deductive closure and another operation of class
closure. This is because every binary R \subseteq AxB induces a Galois
connection between the power sets of A and B, whose two polarities
constitute the two closure operations. We know that this is true for
equational logic, for which deductive closure of a set of equations is
its congruence closure while class closure is HSP, Birkhoff's theorem.
But there is nothing special about equational logic in that regard:
*every* relation of satisfiability comes with such a pair of closure
operations.
Yet another example is that if L is finitary then W is compact, both in
a sense suitably general for this situation. (Due to Gordon
Plotkin--the generality part, that is.)
I don't know if this answers your question at all, but it does make the
point that ostensibly simple interactions between word and object such
as the requirement of a two-valued binary relation of satisfiability can
have nontrivial consequences imposing possibly unexpected limits on
one's freedom to organize word and object.
More information about the FOM
mailing list