[FOM] A question concerning continuous functions
Arnon Avron
aa at tau.ac.il
Mon Jan 27 02:21:28 EST 2003
There is a question concerning the definition(s) of
the concept of a "continuous function" which has bothered
me since I was a first-year student in mathematics. I
believe that this list might be the most appropriate place
to look for an answer.
The question is the following: I think that the first
definition of this notion that each of us
has encountered (and later has given to our own undergraduate
students, at least in the form of an intuitive explanation) is
that a real-valued function defined on some interval is continuous
iff its graph can be drawn without lifting the pen from the
paper (or the chalk from the blackboard). Later, however, we
were given a completely different, analytic definition (using epsilon,
delta, and alternating quantifiers - or something which is equivalent
to it if we assume the axiom of dependent choice). We then started to
work with this official definition, never returning to the original,
intuitive one again. Now what I find amazing is that I have never been
given, (and neither have I found in any textbook I have seen) any
argument why these two notions of a "continuous function" are in fact
equivalent. This does not seem obvious at all, at least to me . More
precisely, it does seem very intuitive to me that a function which is
continuous in the intuitive sense should also be continuous according
to the official definition, but I see no compelling reasons
to believe that the converse is true.
My immediate question is: can anybody provide me with references to
works which discuss this issue and present the reasons for accepting
the identification of the two notions? (What I have in mind is
something similar to the way the case for Church Thesis
is presented in Kleene's "Introduction to Metamathematics" or in
Shoenfield's "mathematical Logic"). I would like, of course, also to
hear any personal answer to (or thoughts about) this question
that you might have.
Let me explain why I think that this question is very relevant
and important to FOM:
1) The fact that I mentioned Church Thesis above is no accident. In
both cases it may be argued that an intuitive, but too vague a notion
has been given a precise, mathematically manageable definition. In
both cases (one may continue arguing) there is no hope of *proving*
the equivalence of the two notions (because of the inherent vagueness
of the intuitive one), but it is possible to present a convincing
evidence for the thesis that the precise definition captures the
intuitive concept. In the case of continuous functions one may point
to basic theorems like: the intermediate value theorem ("second
Bolzano-Cauchy theorem"), the boundness of a continuous function
on a closed finite interval, and the fact that it has a maximum
and a minimum there. Note, however, that unlike the case of
Church Thesis, here we also have strong evidence that the two
notions are *not* identical (e.g. in the form of functions which are
"continuous" but have no derivative in any point of their domains).
I would like to point out again that while almost any textbook
on computability defends Church Thesis in one way or another, authors
of textbooks in analysis seem to feel free from such obligations. Why?
2) In my opinion, the weakest point of Intuitionism, and the reason why
it will never be adopted by most mathematicians (even though many of
them adhere to the importance of constructive proofs) is that it
seems to totally ignore geometric intuitions and concepts. As far as
I understand (and please correct me if I am wrong), intuitionists
have completely abandoned the original, intuitive concept of
continuity in favor of (some constructive version of) the "official"
definition. They have ended up rejecting the classical theorems
mentioned above which provide (in my opinion) the main evidence for
accepting this identity in the first place... Let me add that this
phenomenon provides (for me) another evidence that the two notions
of continuity are not identical.
3) Returning to the comparison with Church Thesis, there is one
big difference in that (at least in my eyes) the intuitive definition
of a continuous function is *not* vague or imprecise (certainly not
as vague and imprecise as the notion of a "mechanically computable
function" had been before Church Thesis was formulated). It is
completely sufficient, in fact, for conveying and understanding the
notion we have in mind. From this point of view, it is even superior
to the official definitions. True: it does seem useless for proving
properties of continuous functions or even for showing that the
elementary functions are continuous. This might be due, however, to
the inherent limitations of using discrete languages (whether formal
or informal) for describing and reasoning about continuous geometrical
objects and phenomena. I suspect (and this is no doubt a *BIG*
speculation) that the incompleteness phenomenon discovered by Goedel
is really due to the unbridgeable gap between our discrete languages
(and proofs) and our geometrical intuitions.
4) According to my best understanding, the main problem in the
foundations of mathematics is (and was) how to justify the use of
infinite objects in mathematics without destroying the absoluteness
and the necessity we like to ascribe to mathematical propositions.
Finite, concrete objects cause no difficulty here (even if there are
certainly philosophers who would be happy to argue to the contrary...).
Infinite objects *are* problematic. Their use involves strong
metaphysical assumptions that one cannot honestly take as necessary
and obvious. Unfortunately, the real numbers, the heart of modern
mathematics, are infinite objects according to any official definition.
Had these definitions told the whole story concerning the reals I would
not have hesitated to dismiss their use as "theology" (or at least
judge their use in science by pragmatical criteria, like we judge
physical theories). However, I do have a strong *geometrical* intuition
concerning the reals and their connection with finite line segments -
and the latter are for me finite, concrete objects (note that what I
call here "a finite line segment" was simply called "line" by Euclid).
According to my views, therefore, it is only geometry that may be able
to provide a real justification and foundation for the real numbers. I
believe, accordingly, that a new synthesis of analog and discrete
reasoning should be taken as the most important foundational challenge.
My question above is, of course, connected with this challenge.
More information about the FOM
mailing list